The American Psychiatric Association (APA) has updated its Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including with new information specifically addressed to individuals in the European Economic Area. As described in the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, this website utilizes cookies, including for the purpose of offering an optimal online experience and services tailored to your preferences.

Please read the entire Privacy Policy and Terms of Use. By closing this message, browsing this website, continuing the navigation, or otherwise continuing to use the APA's websites, you confirm that you understand and accept the terms of the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including the utilization of cookies.

×
Letter to the EditorFull Access

Biology Versus Psychoanalysis

Published Online:

The crude Cartesian dualism decried by Eric R. Kandel, M.D. (1), has been succeeded by much subtler considerations of the relationship between what we still, for lack of better terms, call “mind” and “brain.” For instance, philosophers Frank Jackson (2) and Thomas Nagel (3), among others, have emphasized the degree to which subjective and objective descriptions are fundamentally different, and even irreconcilable, categories of explanation. Scientists aspire to a world view that is maximally objective and value neutral, whereas intrinsic to subjective phenomena are specific points of view and biased interests. In this view, a comprehensive objective science of human behavior may not be feasible. This is not to say that objective factors are irrelevant from a subjective standpoint, only that the former cannot, logically, account for all of experience. The issue then may not be some kind of ethereal substance called “mind” but rather the radical epistemological gulf that subjectivity represents.

The hallmark of psychoanalysis, and really all psychotherapy, is the attempt to fathom and, if possible, to ameliorate a patient’s subjective reality. Psychotherapy entails such entities as self, person, meaning, values, and free will—all of which may be even less reducible to biology than the vaguer notion of “mind.” Psychotherapy presupposes a freedom of subjective will that exists even in the context of great adversity. Psychotropic medication and other somatic treatments are necessary because there are obvious (and sometimes not-so-obvious) limits to freedom of will. The interplay of the two approaches, subjective and objective, touch on paradox and the limits of our understanding, but they are complementary and not mutually exclusive. If this argument turns out to be wrong, and biology does someday fully explain subjectivity, then traditional notions of autonomy and individual freedom will be discounted, psychotherapy will become superfluous, and our views of human beings, self, and other will alter in ways that are difficult to foresee.

Dr. Kandel is right that on experimental grounds, psychoanalysis never has been a science; rather, it is a hodgepodge of psychological theory, history, and literature. He laments the possibility that psychoanalysis may be relegated to the realms of philosophy and literature. His implication is astute, and his article convincingly advocates the replacement with biology of that part of psychoanalysis that has purported to be objective explanation. What remains is a wealth of thought about history, society, and art. In fact, it is notable that the decline of psychoanalysis within psychiatry has been paralleled by its meteoric rise in the fields of aesthetics and literary theory.

Psychoanalysis is being split asunder. Its scientific and objective aspirations, after long and eminent careers as heuristics for empirical research, are in the process of being consumed by biology, whereas its philosophical aspects live on as gloriously as before. It is no wonder that Freud vacillated between scientific and hermeneutical views of his creation, which, at times, he recognized as a loose and unstable amalgam.

References

1. Kandel ER: Biology and the future of psychoanalysis: a new intellectual framework for psychiatry revisited. Am J Psychiatry 1999; 156:505–524AbstractGoogle Scholar

2. Jackson F: What Mary didn’t know. J Philosophy 1986; 83:291–295CrossrefGoogle Scholar

3. Nagel T: Mortal Questions. Cambridge, UK, Cambridge University Press, 1979Google Scholar