The American Psychiatric Association (APA) has updated its Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including with new information specifically addressed to individuals in the European Economic Area. As described in the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, this website utilizes cookies, including for the purpose of offering an optimal online experience and services tailored to your preferences.

Please read the entire Privacy Policy and Terms of Use. By closing this message, browsing this website, continuing the navigation, or otherwise continuing to use the APA's websites, you confirm that you understand and accept the terms of the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including the utilization of cookies.

×
Regular ArticleFull Access

A Date With Death: Management of Time-Based and Contingent Suicidal Intent

Published Online:https://doi.org/10.1176/ajp.155.11.1502

Abstract

Objective:The patient who voices suicidal intent in terms of the future or in terms of certain life contingencies presents special difficulties for the therapist. The authors outline the challenges posed by this problem for assessment, clinical management, and risk management. Method:The authors examined and analyzed case examples from both clinical and risk-management aspects. Results:Problematic cases can be grouped into categories that offer insight as to management. The authors discuss this area and offer suggestions for appropriate clinical responses to this challenge. Conclusions:The authors recommend that therapists 1) treat the expressed “date with death” as a communication to be explored, 2) explore the problem of helplessness while monitoring their own countertransference responses, 3) assess the patient’s competence to inform clinicians about suicidal state, and 4) readily use involuntary commitment. Am J Psychiatry 1998; 155: 1502-1507

The suicidal person often makes conditions for life: if you don’t save me, I’ll die; if I can’t make you happy, I’ll end my life. Such attitudes are central to the patient’s involvement with suicide; if their emergence does not arouse excessive anxiety on the part of the therapist, he is in a position to explore them to therapeutic advantage.

— Hendin (1)

The assessment of suicidal risk is one of the most common and basic procedures in psychiatry, and many discussions of clinical approaches to this determination have been offered (2–7). Although persons at risk for suicide always raise some anxiety in mental health professionals, the appropriate responses by the treaters to this condition are fairly straightforward: assessment of the imminence and seriousness of the risk, evaluation of available resources, and a clinical disposition that addresses both of these realms. Growing clinical experience may alleviate anxiety in this area. Indeed, experience can even guide the therapist through the tricky terrain of suicidal intent as blackmail or coercion: “Admit me to this hospital or I will kill myself” (8).

One class of patients within the larger population of persons at suicidal risk, however, poses special challenges for the clinician and produces anxiety, not only in the novice but even in the experienced professional. These individuals do not present with immediate or imminent risk through suicidal intent or with an obvious “blackmail” goal (“Do this or else”); rather, they link their suicidal intent to a future point—sometimes even a distant future point—or to a particular life situation on a contingent basis. The following examples illustrate more clearly how the core of such a time-based or contingent dynamic might be posed:

“If I don’t feel better by my 30th birthday, I will kill myself.”

“If my mood is not improved by the third year of therapy, I’ll kill myself.”

“If I am not married by 2 years from today, I’ll kill myself.”

“If my wife leaves me, I’ll kill myself.”

For therapists, patients who take such positions pre­sent significant therapeutic resistances, provoke strong countertransference feelings of helplessness and anger, and invite both under- and overreaction. Moreover, the professional literature provides little guidance on how to deal with the dilemmas posed by such patients.

LITERATURE REVIEW

Acute suicidality is a familiar entity in office and hospital practice (9–12). Although examples are less common, the literature has also addressed patients with chronic suicidality—primarily those patients with personality disorders or fixed delusions who are “never not suicidal” (13–16). One of us suggested (17) that acute suicidality is a problem in the psychology of despair, while chronic suicidality is a problem in the psychology of responsibility—that is, despair and responsibility represent the critical issues in the respective cases. This formulation permits conceptualizing approaches to such patients.

The patients who were our focus were neither acute nor chronic. Their self-destructive intent was not imminent; indeed, according to the patients, it could be years away. Nor was the problem actually chronic. The patients were not always, or even often, suicidal; their lethality was contingent on a time or set of circumstances in the future. Such patients may feel no suicidal intention in the present at all, in part, of course, because the wish has been encapsulated into a particular context set in the future. This suggests that one of the elements of contingent suicidality is its effect as a defense against actual immediate suicide.

Farber (2) expands on this last point as follows:

There is a certain kind of person for whom the idea of suicide is a secret and cherished solution to any difficulty life may throw across his path. Suicide is the ace up his sleeve (revealed to no one), the secret possession of which shapes his response to any and every problem. Such a man confronts his life whispering to himself, “If I can’t find a better job, I’ll kill myself.” If my son won’t confide in me, if my daughter flunks her final exams, if my wife forgets my birthday just one more time—I’ll kill myself…because concealment is so vital to his “advantage,” as he conceives it, and therefore his deviousness and dishonesty so virtually impossible to penetrate, he is, I believe, the most difficult of all potential suicides to treat—or help in any way. (p. 126)

This special situation is both contingent and chronic. Here, suicide may represent the ultimate control for the patient when all else has failed.

Cavenar et al. (18) discuss reactions to anniversaries, which are often the occasions chosen for time-based suicidal intent. According to their definition, anniversary reactions are time-specific psychological and, at times, physiological reactions that occur or recur at specific anniversaries in response to a trauma that the individual has experienced in the past and has not effectively mastered. Certain patients with obsessional styles appear to accumulate anniversaries, such that almost any day of the year is regarded as the anniversary of some meaningful event and is thus a point of theoretically increased suicidal risk.

The number and variability of all the foregoing factors combined make the use of involuntary commitment—a common intervention in suicidal cases—highly problematic and ethically complex.

THE PRESENT STUDY

We intend here to present some real but disguised and condensed examples of this problem in clinical practice, to analyze their dynamics, and to suggest both clinical and risk-management approaches.

Case 1. Ms. A. is a middle-aged woman with treatment-refractory depressive disorder, possible bipolar II disorder, borderline personality disorder, and a history of posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD) and bulimia. This combination of factors led to severe intractable depressions. She recently told her therapist that if her condition did not improve after a year of treatment, her agreement not to kill herself would be canceled and she would commit suicide. She constantly wanted to kill herself and practiced the mechanics of hanging herself for the “great day.”

Ms. A’s therapist countered by saying that he did not agree to her plan and that there was always the likelihood that a cingulotomy might help. His intervention was now a point of discussion and conflict in the therapy.

Comment. For Ms. A, as with other patients known to clinicians, death took on the qualities of an object relationship that, paradoxically, permits continued living and provides a sustaining and supportive function. Patients themselves clearly describe how death becomes intrapsychically personified as a kind and helpful healer who “promises” to take away the pain and suffering and to grant blessed relief. The therapist removes or challenges the relationship with such an agent at his or her own peril, since it may be the only relationship in which the patient has any faith. Any interventions made should respect the value of this tie, and the therapist should avoid placing the patient in a position of having to give it up precipitously (e.g., by asserting, “I will put you in the hospital so that you cannot kill yourself”). The therapist should carefully record the rationale for not vigorously opposing this relationship, since opposition might seem to be called for by the standard of care. In addition, the therapist should concretely state that he or she supports the part of the patient that wants to stay alive, even though the patient may feel tempted by death.

Case 2. Ms. B was initially seen while in her thirties for serious and recurrent problems with depression, anxiety, anorexia nervosa and bulimia, alcohol and drug abuse, and borderline personality disorder. She had a history of two suicide attempts, both nearly lethal. In addition, Ms. B had an older sister who had committed suicide some years before, and the patient always became suicidal on or near the anniversary of her sister’s death. Since Ms. B’s sister had died during the summer, the anniversary would often coincide with her therapist’s vacations. As time went on, Ms. B suffered more losses and became suicidal at more frequent anniversary intervals during the year: Christmas, her sister’s birthday, the anniversary of her sister’s death, her mother’s death, and so forth, so that her suicidality was both chronic and contingent. After 10 years of treatment, Ms. B would become suicidal, with intent and plan, from four to six times a year, with frequent hospitalizations. At a certain point, Ms. B again had plans to kill herself; this time she did not plan to live to the end of the year. Before the date on which she threatened to carry out her plan, Ms. B accepted hospitalization in accord with a long-standing contract with her therapist; shortly thereafter, the therapist terminated her therapy for personal reasons. One year after termination, Ms. B communicated to her therapist that she had made some significant changes in her life: she was separated from her husband of 20 years and was no longer in treatment of any kind.

Comment. In this case, Ms. B accepted voluntary hospitalization in anticipation of a “date with death,” in part because of a contract with her therapist and widespread ambivalence about suicide. In addition, the therapist terminated her therapy at that time. The outcome of this case raises the question as to whether Ms. B’s therapy with that particular therapist was somehow overstimulating her, since after termination she appeared to improve.

Case 3. Mr. C., a prison inmate, told a prison mental heath service psychologist that he would commit suicide if he was committed to a treatment center for sexually dangerous persons; hence, this was a contingent suicide plan. Mr. C was, in fact, serving time for a rape conviction but would have soon become eligible for parole. On the other hand, he could be incarcerated for life if committed to the treatment center. Unfortunately, Mr. C did not wait until after his commitment hearing; he killed himself before it was even clear whether or not he would be committed to the treatment center. (Some time previously, Mr. C’s brother had also committed suicide for a different reason.)

Comment. Mr. C’s case presents a valuable teaching point: clinicians themselves should not be too concrete or literal about the specific deadlines and contingencies proffered by the patient as though they were guarantees of continued life until those set points. The underlying depression may overwhelm the patient on occasions other than the patient’s verbalized dates or times.

Case 4. Mr. D, a young single man, “had shot himself in the heart—the bullet indeed grazed his heart, pierced his lung, and came to rest close to his spine. He came into treatment telling [the therapist] that he would give [him] six months to make him less lonely, isolated, and depressed before killing himself. This kind of ultimatum, whether given to a therapist, a lover, or to oneself is designed not merely to bring about the end but to kill whatever relationship may emerge before death. This young man was treatable only when [therapist and patient] focused on the way in which he tried to make [the] relationship one in which he would be dead and therefore challenge or resist any efforts to bring him back to life. Life is not, as it seems, or as the individual often says, unbearable with depression, but may sometimes be inconceivable without it” (cited from Hendin [1], p. 472).

Comment. This case further supports the value of refraining from premature or unilateral attempts to take away the patient’s relationship with death.

Case 5. Ms. E was a middle-aged divorced woman with PTSD, dysthymia, cognitive impairment related to PTSD, and dissociative disorder not otherwise specified. Ms. E’s early history was replete with repeated physical and sexual abuse. She was socially isolated and had made several suicide attempts.

Bad hospital experience led Ms. E’s psychiatrist to agree that he would not hospitalize her against her will on the condition that she speak honestly with him about her suicidal ideation. There were no further suicide attempts, but Ms. E disclosed her long-range plan to kill herself after her youngest child graduated from high school.

Ms. E viewed suicide as a “joyous release from life.” She did not see it as misdirected anger and had given much thought to her decision to end her life. She stated that her children were the only thing that kept her going and felt that she had now done her job of rearing them. Her daughter’s recent serious illness had thwarted her long-term plan. Ms. E made a pact with God that if her daughter lived, she would not kill herself. Her daughter survived, but Ms. E then changed her mind; once again, the clock was ticking. A consultant gave the opinion that preservation of the doctor-patient relationship rather than hospitalization was the most important protective factor against Ms. E’s suicidal impulses and recommended a low-dose antipsychotic to mute her self-destructive voices. Ms. E agreed to the treatment, deferred her plans to end her life, tolerated the medication, and continued to work in therapy.

Comment. Ms. E’s case demonstrates how a suicidal plan can persist despite some clinical improvement and increased insight. Since her suicide plan was child centered, it also appeared changeable in response to a child’s condition. This fact did not seem to decrease the seriousness of her plan, however.

In the Netherlands, where assisted suicide is an accepted medical intervention, examples appear of what must be styled “iatrogenic contingent suicide.” For practitioners, such cases pose different problems from those posed by patient-set contingencies, as the following examples show.

Case 6. Ms. F, a social worker in Holland, attempted suicide after her son had committed suicide. She visited several mental health professionals, all of whom told her to see a psychiatrist. According to Dutch traditions, she sought assisted suicide from a psychiatrist, who “made a commitment to help her with her suicide if she would truly explore her life in their sessions and still felt she wanted to die. . . . There was no trace of the psychotic in her” (19, p. 62). After 30 sessions over a 1-month period, which sometimes included her close relatives, Ms. F decided to proceed with assisted suicide and followed through with her decision (19).

Case 7. Hendin (19) describes an interview with Rene Diek­stra, professor of psychology at the University of Leyden:

Diekstra told me of several patients that he had been able to involve in psychotherapy on the promise that if treatment did not work he would assist in their suicide. . . . I pointed out that many patients come into therapy with sometimes conscious but more often unconscious fantasies that cast the therapist in the role of their executioner. A commitment on the therapist’s part to become executioner if treatment fails plays into and reinforces these fantasies. It may also play into the therapist’s illusion that if he cannot cure the patient, no one else can either (pp. 56–57).

Comment. The foregoing discussion displays the problems with the therapist’s application of contingencies to a patient’s suicide. Clearly, it may be valuable to the patient for the therapist to establish a moratorium on the suicidal act and to separate depressive colorations from the decision making (20). Thus, one might say to a suicidal patient, “I know I can’t stop you from killing yourself, but it would be a pity if you made such an important decision while depression was clouding your judgment. Let’s get you out of the depression and then, if you still want to kill yourself, I can’t stand in your way” (J. Ewalt, personal communication, 1968). Such a negotiated moratorium asserts the truth—that determined persons cannot be stopped. It then goes on not only to postpone the irreversible but also to suggest indirectly a way out of the depression—a future-oriented perspective usually clouded by that very depression.

In contrast, however, clinicians forged alliances with the two Dutch patients described earlier around the promised surcease of dying, indeed, with the psychiatrist’s help, if treatment failed. In the Dutch cases, the authors address neither the possibility of subtle incompetence (21) in the patients nor the possibility of treatment with electroconvulsive therapy in resistant depressions. We could advance a strong clinical counterargument that psychiatrists should never support suicide, but should acknowledge the human impossibility of preventing it.

DISCUSSION

Ethical Dilemmas

These cases raise ethical dilemmas for the treating psychiatrist. When, if ever, is a chronic psychiatric illness analogous to an incurable physical illness? Certainly, psychic pain can be as debilitating as physical pain, and some patients may not respond to treatment. Hendin (22) refers to one type of suicidal patient as the patient who sees himself or herself as already dead. Often such a patient presents with very little affect with which the therapist can work. Another type of patients who are often unresponsive to treatment are those patients with certain personality disorders. Studies of psychological autopsies (postmortem reviews of the apparent psychology of the suicidal patient) suggest that up to one-third of suicide victims had personality disorders (23). Suicidal patients with personality disorders, anxiety disorders, or substance abuse disorders are less likely to experience hopelessness than to experience cognitive distortion (24).

Another ethical concern is to what extent psychiatrists should intervene when a patient’s date with death approaches. Should we respect a rational patient’s right to autonomy and self-determination? How do we reconcile such respect with our duty to protect, to prevent impulsive and irreversible steps (suicide) in response to an often reversible condition (depression)? While we would not take the position of colluding in suicide, as in the example of the Dutch psychiatrist, we recognize that patients who are really intent on suicide will find a way. Absent an immediate crisis that is pushing the patient over the edge, brief hospitalization may not have any deterrent value, as these patients can always reschedule their dates with death.

Studies of therapists’ attitudes towards elective suicide show that a surprising number of them support the notion of rational suicide and believe that people have a right to choose both the quality and duration of life (25, 26). Psychologists in one study, however, were more likely to take action to prevent suicide in the case of a man with psychological pain than in the case of one with physical pain from terminal cancer. Werth and Cobia (25) suggest that when therapists face cases of “rational suicide,” their duty may be more to assess the rationality of the client than to protect him or her. Here, a latent question of competence to make choices appears to be at issue.

Several authors have discussed just what should go into such an assessment. Motto (27) proposed that the intended act must be based on a realistic assessment of one’s life situation and that ambivalence about suicide must be minimal.

Recommendations

Each of the case vignettes noted earlier is followed by specific risk-management suggestions for the issues raised therein. It may yet be helpful to offer some general suggestions about these clinical dilemmas.

First, the patients described in this study were not only planning suicide but were telling the clinicians about it. A patient intent on death might well not disclose this plan; about 60% of the population who commit suicide do so without telling any professional (28). Thus, we may first approach the patient’s date with death as communication: “What are you trying to tell me about your condition by setting this deadline?” Exploration may yield useful clinical data about significant others, lost sources of former pleasure, and similar information; sharing these issues with the therapist may renew the patient’s attachment to life.

From one viewpoint, a date with death is also an attempt to blackmail fate, the world, or other people. Just as patients who manipulate others feel unentitled to ask directly, patients who attempt through blackmail to gain power to control the environment may feel helpless to control anything. Thus, a date with death offers such a patient a feeling of mastery over helplessness. Opening the topic of felt helplessness may enable the therapist to establish empathic contact with a patient whose date with death appears to hold the clinician at a distance, helpless in his or her own right; shared helplessness may provide a pathway to empathic connection. Since suicide may be the patient’s way of communicating unbearable psychic pain, the clinician must acknowledge the pain, letting the patient know that it can be borne by the dyad.

The problem of helplessness constitutes a powerful argument for avoiding ineffectual power struggles with patients about their suicide plans. Indeed, power struggles over suicide may represent a resistance to therapeutic engagement on the issues underlying suicidal feelings, closing off discussion, as in case 5. While involuntary hospitalization of patients for their protection may certainly be necessary at some point, careful pacing of the therapy and the teaching of cognitive and behavioral skills may allow patients to discuss and then to deal effectively with unbearable affects while remaining an outpatient.

Countertransference factors including projection may lead to the clinician’s feeling blackmailed even when this is not the patient’s intent; the patient in a suicidal state is often too caught up in the affect to consider the impact on others.

The assessment of competence is a central consideration in dealing with patients, not only at the very end, when “competence to commit suicide” may be at issue, but also at earlier stages, when patients’ competence to choose to inform or not to inform their clinicians about their status may critically determine joint decision making. Almost every jurisdiction permits competent patients to refuse life-saving interventions by other medical specialties; presumably, a competent patient could refuse life-saving psychiatric intervention as well (29). While not established, this principle has been successfully utilized in the defense of suicide malpractice cases in at least six states. The decisive question is whether the patient suffers from the subtle incompetence created by masked depression (21) or an equally subtle psychosis. Careful assessment can answer this question; equally careful documentation can preserve the answer.

Because the patient is presenting with intent and a plan, though a future-oriented one, clinicians may be able to draw some comfort from the fact that their attempts at involuntary commitment at or near the critical date can almost always be justified, even in ambiguous situations, although obviously the endpoint would be extremely unclear. This freedom, paradoxically, may permit the clinician not to commit the patient unnecessarily. In some jurisdictions, commitment in these cases would be far more difficult, especially in locales where a previous overt act of suicidal intent is required for commitment. Since it would represent the less conservative action, the decision not to commit should be carefully reasoned in the record. Clinicians should seek active, ongoing consultation or supervision to avoid the pitfall of their own anger at being blackmailed—a common and understandable reaction, but one that may threaten clinical judgment. Consultation here (and at earlier points) is valuable in such situations and also prudent in the event that the patient commits suicide, and a suit is brought against the clinician.

CONCLUSIONS

Accepting the patient’s pain and sense of hopelessness is not the same as acceding to his or her wish to commit suicide; the psychiatrist must always hold out hope. At the same time, it may be therapeutic and realistic to let patients know that one can not ultimately prevent their suicides. We believe that a psychiatrist should never condone a patient’s decision to commit suicide; however, there may be cases where the psychiatrist can justify not intervening and accepting the patient’s stated wish.

Under the Damoclean sword of the patient’s date with death, the therapist may wish to follow the above recommendations in the service of maintaining the holding environment despite the pressures brought to bear. While not all suicides can be prevented, the above approaches may at least permit the clinician to remain in the therapeutic relationship at all times while attending to risk-management considerations.

Received July 18, 1997; revisions received Dec. 8, 1997, and March 31, 1998; accepted April 17, 1998. From the Department of Psychiatry, Harvard Medical School, Boston; and the Program in Psychiatry and the Law; Massachusetts Mental Health Center. Address reprint requests to Dr. Gutheil, Massachusetts Mental Health Center, 74 Fenwood Rd., Boston, MA 02115. The authors thank Drs. John T. Maltsberger, Teri Rumpf, Michael Sharpston, and Larry Strasburger for comments and suggestions; and Ms. Ellen Lewy for essential assistance with the manuscript.

References

1. Hendin HH: Psychotherapy and suicide. Am J Psychother 1981; 35:469–480Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

2. Farber LH: Despair and the life of suicide. Rev Existential Psychol Psychiatry 1962; 2:125–139Google Scholar

3. Maltsberger JT: Suicide Risk: The Formulation of Clinical Judgment. New York, New York University Press, 1986Google Scholar

4. Havens LL: Recognition of suicidal risks through the psychological examination. N Engl J Med 1967; 276:210–215Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

5. Beck AT, Kovacs M, Weissman A: Assessment of suicidal intention: the Scale for Suicide Ideation. J Consult Clin Psychol 1979; 47:343–352Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

6. Motto JA, Heilbron DC, Juster RP: Development of a clinical instrument to estimate suicide risk. Am J Psychiatry 1985; 142:680–686LinkGoogle Scholar

7. Clark DC, Fawcett J: An empirically based model of suicide risk assessment for patients with affective disorder, in Suicide and Clinical Practice. Edited by Jacobs D. Washington, DC, American Psychiatric Press, 1992, pp 55–74Google Scholar

8. Sifneos P: Manipulative suicide. Psychiatr Q 1966; 40:525–537Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

9. Fawcett J: Predictors of early suicide: identification and appropriate intervention. J Clin Psychiatry 1988; 49:7–8MedlineGoogle Scholar

10. Stone AA: A syndrome of serious suicidal intent. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1960; 3:331–339CrossrefGoogle Scholar

11. Stone AA, Shein HM: Psychotherapy of the hospitalized suicidal patient. Am J Psychother 1968; 22:15–25Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

12. Ringel E: The presuicidal syndrome. Suicide Life Threat Behav 1976; 6:131–145MedlineGoogle Scholar

13. Basescu S: The threat of suicide in psychotherapy. Am J Psychother 1965; 19:99–105Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

14. Olin HS: Psychotherapy of the chronically suicidal patient. Am J Psychother 1976; 30:570–575Crossref, MedlineGoogle Scholar

15. Schwartz DA: The suicidal character. Psychiatr Q 1979; 5:64–70CrossrefGoogle Scholar

16. Kernberg OF: Clinical management of suicidal potential in borderline patients, in Severe Personality Disorders. New Haven, Conn, Yale University Press, 1984, pp 254–263Google Scholar

17. Gutheil TG: Medicolegal pitfalls in the treatment of borderline patients. Am J Psychiatry 1985; 142:9–14LinkGoogle Scholar

18. Cavenar JO Jr, Nash JL, Maltbie AA: Anniversary reactions masquerading as manic-depressive illness. Am J Psychiatry 1977; 134:1273–1276LinkGoogle Scholar

19. Hendin HH: Seduced by Death: Doctors, Patients, and the Dutch Cure. New York, WW Norton, 1997Google Scholar

20. Bursztajn H, Gutheil TG, Warren MJ, Brodsky A: Depression, self-love, time and the “right” to suicide. Gen Hosp Psychiatry 1986; 8:90–96Google Scholar

21. Gutheil TG, Bursztajn H: Clinicians’ guidelines for assessing and presenting subtle forms of patient incompetence in legal settings. Am J Psychiatry 1986; 143:1020–1023LinkGoogle Scholar

22. Hendin H: Psychiatric emergencies, in Comprehensive Textbook of Psychiatry. Edited by Freedman A, Kaplan A. Baltimore, Williams & Wilkins, 1967, pp 1170–1178Google Scholar

23. Bronisch T: The typology of personality disorders: diagnostic problems and their relevance for suicidal behavior. Crisis 1996; 17(2):55–58Google Scholar

24. Mendonca JD, Holden RR: Are all suicidal ideas closely linked to hopelessness? Acta Psychiatr Scand 1966; 93:245–251Google Scholar

25. Werth JL, Cobia DC: Empirically based criteria for rational suicide: a survey of psychotherapists. Suicide Life Threat Behav 1995; 25:231–240MedlineGoogle Scholar

26. Werth JL, Liddle BJ: Psychotherapists’ attitudes toward suicide. Psychotherapy: Theory, Research, and Practice 1994; 31:440–448CrossrefGoogle Scholar

27. Motto J: The right to suicide: a psychiatrist’s view. Life-Threatening Behavior 1972; 2:183–188Google Scholar

28. Jacobs D: Suicide and Clinical Practice. Washington, DC, American Psychiatric Press, 1992Google Scholar

29. Gutheil TG, Bursztajn H, Brodsky A: The multi-dimensional assessment of dangerousness: competence assessment in patient care and liability prevention. Bull Am Acad Psychiatry Law 1986; 14:123–129MedlineGoogle Scholar